Resources

Lesson 5: Descartes and Aftermath

RETURN TO CLASS RESOURCE OVERVIEW

Choose Another Lesson

close

Lessons

  1. Lesson 1: Hippocratic Foundations

    Read More

    Students examine the biologically-focused foundational concepts and explanatory strategies of Western medicine first inscribed in the works of Hippocrates. Close

  2. Lesson 2: Late Ancient and Medieval Medical Views of Mind and Body

    Read More

    Students explore Hippocrates’ principal successor Galen among the late ancient medical writers, Galen’s departures from Hippocrates’ ideas on mind and body, and Avicenna's and Maimonides’ continuation of Galen’s approach among the medieval writers.Close

  3. Lesson 3: Mind and Body in Renaissance and Early Modern Medicine

    Read More

    Students look at the framework of medical belief and practice in the late 15th, 16th, and early 17th centuries and focuses on the persistence of older ways of thinking about the mind-body relationship despite certain new developments in medical science. Students also examine early modern court records for the contemporary lay perspective on “insanity.”Close

  4. Lesson 4: Mind and Body in Shakespeare and his Contemporaries

    Read More

    Students examine Shakespeare’s own ideas and compares them to those of his contemporaries, again focusing on the mind-body theme. Although there was great general continuity between ancient, medieval, and early modern ideas on both basic human biology and strategies for explaining disease symptoms, different authors sometimes chose to emphasize the mind or the body to different degrees.Close

  5. Lesson 5: Descartes and Aftermath

    Read More

    Students closely study Rene Descartes’s innovative philosophical ideas on mind-body dualism as a challenge to the beliefs about human behavior and disease causation commonly accepted in classical, medieval, and early modern medicine. Students also look at the impact of Descartes’s ideas on medicine in the late 17th and 18th century and beyond.Close

  6. Lesson 6: The Modern Era

    Read More

    Students explore broad themes in the development of modern medicine from ca. 1800 to the present and concentrates on the general triumph of biological approaches to both physical and mental diseases in that period. The development of modern biologically-based psychiatric therapy for mood and behavioral disorders and mental illness underscores a parallel between ideas in our own time and many of the ideas in Shakespeare’s. This lesson also includes a list of topics and resources for students to take on research papers, small group presentations, or classroom debates.Close

  7. About the Author

Introduction

Mind and body were only partially distinct conceptually before the philosopher Rene Descartes (1596–1650) introduced what many regarded as radically new philosophical ideas. He claimed that mind and body were fundamentally different substances, body being material and passive while mind was immaterial and active. This philosophical position is commonly called “mind-body dualism” or “Cartesian dualism.” For Descartes and his 17th century contemporaries, this approach not only posed a fundamental challenge to long-standing beliefs about physical reality and human nature, but also had complicated implications for medicine.

Claims about the impact of Cartesian dualism on medicine are often overstated and oversimplified. Some authors say that it created a dichotomy that severed mind from body and left earlier, more holistic medical ideas in disarray. But there is no evidence that Descartes actually had this effect. His dualism was in reality an “interactionist” dualism, and much of his work was devoted to explaining how mind and body interact with and influence one another. His treatise on Passions of the Soul (1649) was devoted to explaining this in great detail. Descartes defined passion as the mind's perception of a previously occurring set of movements in the blood or other body fluids. Then using a mechanical model of the human organism building on Harvey’s circulation of the blood and breaking sharply with humoralism, Descartes connected each of the basic emotions to specific physiological causes. His philosophical purpose was to emphasize man’s ability to control his passions and live more rationally and ethically because passions were primarily bodily events that could be allowed to crest and crash like waves without necessarily forcing harmful human response. The human mind could exercise its will by waiting out the rising and falling of the emotional waves or by forcing their currents back into more constructive pathways.

Descartes’ philosophical work thus emphasized explicitly that mind and emotion, while separate from the material body, are also closely associated with the body and strongly interactive with it. It was especially important to Descartes that mind can willfully and self-consciously act upon the body. These ideas tended to emphasize will and personality in ways that underscored human psychology as operating in a separate domain from biology rather than being subject to it and determined by it, as in the humoral theory of traditional medicine.

Read More

In the century and a half after Descartes, medicine followed three different paths. Those who followed the first path tried to build on Descartes to create systems of medical mechanism or “iatromechanism” in which a mechanically functioning body replaced the humor-dominated body of traditional medical theory. This was represented by physicians like Giorgio Baglivi (1668–1707) and Friedrich Hoffmann (1660–1742), the latter publishing Fundamenta Medicinae (“Fundamentals of Medicine”) in 1695 as a iatromechanical textbook. Those who followed the second path rejected medical mechanism as too theoretical and too far removed from the realities of everyday medicine. They attended to the details of clinical practice and tried to construct “natural histories” of disease as they observed and recorded those histories over time at the patient’s bedside. Thomas Sydenham (1624–1689) in the 17th century and William Heberden (1710–1801) in the 18th were good representatives of this pathway. The third path was pursued by those who focused on applying anatomical knowledge through postmortem dissection to the retrospective understanding of pathological symptoms. This was generally called “pathoanatomy” and its principal 18th century representative was Giovanni Battista Morgagni (1682–1771), author of De Sedibus et Causis Morborum (“On the Seats and Causes of Diseases”) published in 1761.

Those who travelled the first two paths accepted Cartesian dualism as a reality and gave plenty of room in medicine for the psychological influences of mind and emotions on the onset, course, and treatment of disease. Those on the third path either ignored psychological influences and concentrated on biology alone by studying disordered anatomical structures without allowing a role for the influence of the immaterial mind, or they investigated the anatomy of the brain and nervous system in order to make normal and abnormal anatomy the causal foundation of human thought and behavior without resorting to mind-body dualism. Work of this last kind led in the direction of exclusive biological “materialism” and was represented by Julien Offray de La Mettrie’s (1709–1751) L'Homme Machine (“Man Machine,” 1748). Jerome Gaub (1705–1780) countered La Mettrie in his dualistic De Regimine Mentis (“On the Influence of the Mind,” 1763). Gaub’s approach was dominant in the late 18th century, but over time LaMettrie’s position gradually came to seem less radical and more mainstream. Close

Readings

  • Descartes, Rene. Philosophical Work. Translated by E.S. Haldane and D.R.T. Ross, Vol. I. New York: Dover, 1955, 331-356.
  • Hoffmann, Friedrich. Fundamenta Medicinae. Translated and Introduced by Lester S. King. London: Macdonald, 1971, 39-47, 55-58, 103-108.
  • Porter, Roy. The Greatest Benefit to Mankind: A Medical History of Humanity. New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 1997, 217-219, 228-231, 246-257, 263-264.
  • Rather, L.J. Mind and Body in Eighteenth Century Medicine: A Study Based on Jerome Gaub’s De Regimine Mentis. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1965, 53-56, 70-71, 105-107, 140-142, 173-175.

Discussion Questions

  1. In Passions of the Soul Descartes says that because men have souls and dogs do not, men can exercise much greater control over their emotions because dogs can only react by biological instinct whereas men can impose self-conscious, willful restraint. Descartes writes “[W]hen a dog sees a partridge he is naturally disposed to run towards it … But nevertheless setters are usually so trained that the sight of a partridge causes them to stop … [And] since we can with a little industry change the movement of the brain in animals deprived of reason, it is evident that we can do so yet more in the case of men, and that even those who have the feeblest souls can acquire a very absolute dominion over all their passions …” (p.356)

How does Descartes’ approach influence our expectation of one’s self control over her or his emotions?

  1. How does focusing on self-awareness and the exercise of will serve to separate the domain of psychology from the domain of biology? Does a strongly biological approach to human behavior and personality as in humoral theory significantly reduce or even eliminate our sense of control and responsibility for our own actions?
  1. Iatromechanical systems like Hoffmann’s represented the first-developed post-humoral medical theories. They also incorporated Harvey’s discovery of blood circulation and Descartes’s mechanical explanation of physiological processes. Yet these “modern” systems also carried over much of traditional medicine, as when Hoffman writes “When humors cannot properly circulate or be discharged through suitable vessels, they stagnate and become corrupt … [and] from this are produced plethora, disproportions … and many resulting diseases. (p. 42) … Sometimes it greatly conduces to health to induce vomiting, to sweat, and to drink good wine a little freely.” (p. 104) Given these details of Hoffman’s system, what explains the appeal of iatromechanism to his contemporaries?
  1. Why did physicians like Sydenham and Heberden so vigorously reject theoretical speculations in medicine, especially given the reality that new systems like iatromechanism primarily served as replacements for what by the later 17th century was increasingly perceived as “old-fashioned” humoral theory? In what sense could Sydenham and Heberden be said to have revived the tradition of “bedside Hippocratism”?
  1. Postmortem pathoanatomy such as Morgagni’s had the advantage of applying modern anatomical knowledge to medicine in a practical way. What were the limitations of pathoanatomy? Why was the stethoscope (invented around 1800), which allowed physicians to “see” anatomical abnormalities while the patient was still alive, hailed as a great leap forward?
  2. Why were physicians who relied on either iatromechanical systems or close bedside observation more likely to “see” the influence of psychological factors in the course of illness and treatment than physicians who relied heavily on pathoanatomy and only looked silently at and probed biological structures? What role do spoken words play in medicine that is sensitive to patients’ emotional experiences, whether used by patients to convey their feelings to their physicians or by physicians to offer comfort, reassurance, and hope?